Does a Scientific View of Ourselves Undercut Science?

I’ve been reading “Human Freedom and ‘Emergence’ ” by the Stanford neurobiologist William T. Newsome. Newsome’s leading question is “What are we to make of human freedom when, from a scientific point of view, all forms of behavior are increasingly seen as the causal products of cellular interactions within the central nervous system . . . ?”

Newsome is particularly concerned with a point he quotes from a 1927 work of J. B. S. Haldane: “If my mental processes are determined wholly by the motions of atoms in my brain, I have no reason to suppose my beliefs are true . . . and hence I have no reason for supposing my brain to be composed of atoms.” Newsome takes this point to suggest that a consistent scientist must make room for free will. But he recognizes that a consistent scientist must make such room without supposing there are exceptions to what science shows us about the laws that apply to the motions of atoms. These two demands seem to be in considerable tension.

Newsome seeks to resolve this tension by distinguishing between “constraint” and “determination”. His example is MS Word. Newsome says the operation of this program is constrained by the operations of transistors, resistors, capacitors, and power supplies of the computer that’s executing the program. This means that everything that happens while the program is running depends on how these items work. And the way they work is completely accounted for by their physical properties and the laws of nature that relate those properties. But Newsome also says that “the most incisive understanding of Microsoft Word lies at the higher level of organization of the software.” The behavior of computers “is determined at a higher level of organization – the software – not by the laws of physics or the principles of electronic circuitry.”

In my view, this is an interesting example, because it actually shows us how to undercut Haldane’s point and resolve Newsome’s worry without having to make the puzzling distinction between constraint and determination.

Why do I say the distinction is puzzling? Because “determination” is a term that suggests causation. (That is, for example what Haldane means by “determined” in the sentence Newsome quotes.) But, first, that’s not what Newsome means by this term: “determination”, according to Newsome’s explanation, only means that there are higher level descriptions that can be used to express useful regularities. (Descriptions “at a higher level” do not refer to the small parts of what’s being described.) And, second, “determination” cannot add any causes to what the lower level provides. If it did add anything, there would be something that happened that was inconsistent with the constraints imposed by the laws that apply to the behavior of the small parts (the transistors, capacitors, and so on).

Newsome agrees that everything that happens during the execution of MS Word is consistent with the laws of operation of the small parts of the computer on which it is running. It is also clear that what happens can be described at a higher level at which useful regularities can be expressed. For example, a certain series of keystrokes always results in highlighting a portion of text. A following press of the ‘delete’ key removes the highlighted text; a following click on the paperclip does something else, and so on.

The moral that these facts illustrate is this: A thing whose small parts operate according to ordinary physical laws can have regularities describable at a higher level, provided its small parts are organized in the proper way. There is thus no conflict between holding (1) that everything in a brain happens as a result of its small physical parts (e.g., neurons, synapses, glial cells, neurotransmitters) operating according to physical laws and (2) there is a higher level description of what brains provide that explains how we normally perceive accurately and often reason correctly. Of course, atoms and molecules that are *not* organized in a very special way do not lead to accurate perceptions and reasonable conclusions. But that does not show that properly organized systems of atoms and molecules cannot conform their outputs to evidence and logic.

Because (1) and (2) are consistent, Haldane was wrong to think that we could not have good reasons for our beliefs (including those about atoms and brains) if our beliefs are caused by the motions of atoms in our brains. (The quotation does not say that many of these motions are ultimately caused by inputs to our senses, but Haldane surely would not have denied that.)

“Free will” is used by many thinkers in many senses – that’s why I avoid using that term, except when I write about the views of others who do use it. One of its senses requires that there be departure from causation. In *that* sense of the term, it should be evident that “free will” is something we do *not* want when we are doing science. What we want is that our beliefs about what is in the world should be caused – namely, caused by the things that we believe are there. If our beliefs about the world were cut loose from being caused by what is in the world, we could only expect to have erroneous beliefs about the world.

[Newsome’s essay appears in Nancey Murphy, George F. R. Ellis, and Timothy O’Connor, eds., Downward Causation and the Neurobiology of Free Will (Berlin: Springer-Verlag, 2009), pp. 53-62.]

One Response to Does a Scientific View of Ourselves Undercut Science?

  1. Eddie Madden says:

    Great blog you have heree

Leave a Reply

Fill in your details below or click an icon to log in:

WordPress.com Logo

You are commenting using your WordPress.com account. Log Out /  Change )

Twitter picture

You are commenting using your Twitter account. Log Out /  Change )

Facebook photo

You are commenting using your Facebook account. Log Out /  Change )

Connecting to %s

%d bloggers like this: